COAS
Center for Open Access in Science (COAS)
OPEN JOURNAL FOR STUDIES IN PHILOSOPHY (OJSP)

ISSN (Online) 2560-5380 * ojsp@centerprode.com

OJSP Home

2021 - Volume 5 - Number 1


Parmenides on the True and Right Names of Being

Mostafa Younesie * younesie_7@yahoo.com * ORCID: 0000-0002-7427-2282
Independent scholar in Classical Greek Philosophy of Language, Philadelphia, USA

Open Journal for Studies in Philosophy, 2021, 5(1), 1-18 * https://doi.org/10.32591/coas.ojsp.0501.01001y
Received: 14 February 2021 ▪ Accepted: 12 April 2021 ▪ Published Online: 15 April 2021

LICENCE: Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.

ARTICLE (Full Text - PDF)


ABSTRACT:
Parmenides as a knowing mortal (F I. 3) writes a philosophical-poetic account of a travelogue in which distinctive voices (F. 2) that are a mixture of myth and logos come out of an unnamed goddess (F I. 23) who didactically speaks with an unnamed young man as her direct listener and addressee (F II. 1) in order to reveal for him different spheres and routes (F II. 2) of inquiry about a specific referent. In the hybrid and tailored account of the immortal about a specific subject-matter, such as being, we can read different approaches of the thoughtful mortals through the narration of the goddess, and the idea of the immortal herself. And exactly when thoughtful mortals want to introduce their thinking and understanding of the “referent” in human lingual terms they appeal to the act of naming and making names, though there is no explicit account by the immortal about her approach for lingual expressing of the referent. Such an account gives us some useful and distinctive hints about Parmenides’ conception as a mortal about naming/names which makes his conception in a specific position in regard to the other pertinent and close words, such as ἔπος/ἔπεα, ῥῆμα, ἔργον, καλεῖν, λόγος and Presocratic thinkers like Heraclitus, Democritus, and Empedocles. According to the immortal’s account, in relation to naming and names thoughtful mortals can be classified mainly into two groups: (1) Those who are in Aletheia are informed of the distinctive features of the referent that is a “totality” and should be able to make “true” names for it but fail (F8. 38-39). If they succeeded, then their naming and names are true/ ἀληθῆ; and (2) those who are in Doxa think to know the features of the referent that is a “dual” and accordingly thoughtful mortals make names. Though all of names that are made are not unacceptable, one set is acceptable/χρεών (F 8. 54). As a result, we can infer that if Parmenides as a thoughtful mortal wants to express his thought about eon in lingual terms, he should appeal to naming and making names for they have specific dynamis (F IX. 2—a term that appears in Plato’s Cratylus 394b) in communicating the nature of any specific referent. The first best situation or Aletheia is where on the basis of his “knowledge”, he can communicate the distinctive features of eon in names and thereby make “true” names. Besides, there is the second best or Doxa, where he can communicate his “beliefs” about the essence and essential features of eon in names and make “acceptable” names.

KEY WORDS: Parmenides, poem, name, naming, true, right.

CORRESPONDING AUTHOR:
Mostafa Younesie, Independent scholar in Classical Greek Philosophy of Language. Philadelphia, UNITED STATES. E-mail: younesie_7@yahoo.com.


REFERENCES:

Ademollo, F. (2011). The Cratylus of Plato: A commentary. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Ademollo, F. (2015). Names, verbs, and sentences in ancient Greek philosophy. In M. A. Cameron & R. Stainton (Eds.), Linguistic content: New essays on the history of philosophy of language, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Atherton, C. (1998). Form and content in didactic poetry. Bari: Levante.

Austin, S.(2007). Parmenides and the history of dialectic: Three essays. Las Vegas: Parmenides Publishing.

Barthes, R. (1993). Mythologies. London: Vintage.

Beaney, M. (1997). Frege reader. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell Publishing.

Benardete, S. (1965). XPH and ΔEI in Plato and others. Glotta, 43(3/4), 285-298.

Bredlow, L. A. (2011). Parmenides and the grammar of being. Classical Philology, 106(4), 283-298.

Buck, C. D. (1915). Words of speaking and saying in the Indo-European languages: First & Second Papers. The American Journal of Philology, 36(1), 1-18.

Burnyeat, A. M. F. (1982). Idealism and Greek philosophy: What Descartes saw and Berkeley missed. The Philosophical Review, 91(1), 3-40.

Cherubin, R. (2001). Legein, noein and to eon in Parmenides. Ancient Philosophy, 21, 277-303.

Cherubin, R. (2005). Light, night, and the opinions of mortals: Parmenides B8.51-61 and B9. Ancient Philosophy, Vol.25, No. 1, 1-23.

Colavito, J. (2011). The orphic argonautica. Lulu.com. Retrieved from https://www.lulu.com/shop/jason-colavito/the-orphic-argonautica/paperback/product-17grz4dy.html.

Cordero, N. (Ed.). (2012). Parmenides, venerable and awesome. Las Vegas: Parmenides Publishing.

Cosgrove, M. R. (1974). The ΚΟΥΡΟΣ Motif in "Parmenides": B 1.24. Phronesis, Vol. 19, No. 1, 81-94.

Cosgrove, M. R. (2011). The unknown knowing man: Parmenides, B1.3. The Classical Quarterly New Series, Vol. 61, No. 1, 28-47.

Coxon, A. H. (2009). The fragments of Parmenides: A critical text with introduction, and translation, the ancient testimonia and a commentary. Assen: Van Gorcum.

Cunliffe, R. J. (1924). A lexicon of the Homeric dialect. Norman, Oklahoma: University of Oklahoma Press.

Detienne, M. (1996). The masters of truth in Archaic Greece (J. Lloyd, Trans.). New York: Zone Books.

Diels, H. (1910). Die anfänge der philologie bei den Griechen. Leipzig: B.G. Teubner.

Dimock, G. E., & Murray, A. T. (1995). Homer: The Odyssey. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Foley, H. P. (1994). The Homeric hymn to Demeter: Translation, commentary, and interpretive essays. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Fournier, H. (1946). Les verbes dire en grec ancien. Paris: Klincksieck.

Frère, J. (2017). Mortals (βροτοí) according to Parmenides. In Lawrence J. Trudeau (Ed.), Classical and Medieval Literature Criticism, Vol. 185.

Gianvittorio, L. (2013). Sprechen und Verstehen bei Heraklit und Parmenides. Mnemosyne, 66, 1-29.

Goff, R. (1972). Saying and being with Heidegger and Parmenides. Man and World, 5(1), 62-78.

Gonzalez, F. J. (1995). The third way: New directions in Platonic studies. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

Graeser, A. (1977). On language, thought, and reality in ancient Greek philosophy. Dialectica, 31(3/4), 359-388.

Graham, D. W. (2010). The texts of early Greek philosophy (Part I). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Heidegger, M. (1993). Basic writings,Second Edition, Revised and Expanded by David Farrell Krell. New York: Harper Collins Publishers.

Heidegger, M. (2000). Introduction to metaphysics. (G. Fried and R. F. H. Polt, Trans.). New Haven: Yale University Press.

Jaynes, J. (2000). The origin of consciousness in the breakdown of the bicameral mind. Houghton Mifflin.

Kahn, C. H. (1966). The Greek verb “to be” and the concept of being. Foundations of Language, 2(3), 245-265.

Kraus, M. (1987). Name und Sache: Ein Problem im frühgriechischen Denken. Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing.

Lesher, J. H. (1984). Parmenides’ critique of thinking: The Poluderis Elenchos of Fragment 7. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 2, 1-30.

Liddell-Scott-Jones Greek-English Lexicon Online. Retrieved from https://stephanus.tlg.uci.edu/lsj/

Mason, R. (1988). Parmenides and language. Ancient Philosophy, 8, 149-166.

Messina, G. (1987). Index Parmenideus. Genova: Bozzi editore.

Miller, M. (1999). Platonic mimesis. In T. M. Falkner, N. Felson & D. Konstan (Eds.), Contextualizing classics: Ideology, performance, dialogue: Essays in honor of John J. Peradotto. Lanham, MD: Rowman Littlefield.

Morgan, K. A. (2000). Myth and philosophy from the pre-Socratics to Plato. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Most, G. W. (2006). Theogony: Works and days: Testimonia. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Mourelatos, A. P. D. (1974). The pre-Socratics: A collection of critical essays. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Mourelatos, A. P. D. (2008). The route of Parmenides. Las Vegas: Parmenides Publishing.

Murray, A. T., & Wyatt, W. F. (1978). Homer: The Iliad. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Nagy, G. (1983). Sema and noesis: Some illustrations. Arethusa, 16(1/2), 35-55.

Notopoulos, J. A. (1949). Parataxis in Homer: A new approach to Homeric literary criticism. Transactions and Proceedings of the American Philological Association, 80, 1-23.

Nussbaum, M. C. (1979). Eleatic conventionalism and Philolaus on the conditions of thought. Harvard Studies in Classical Philology, 83, 63-108.

Osborne, C. (1998). Was verse the default form for Presocratic philosophy? in Catherine Atherton (ed.,), Form and Content in Didactic Poetry. Levante.

Owens, J. (1975). Naming in Parmenides. In C. J. de Vogel, J. Mansfeld & L. M. de Rijk (Eds.), Kephalaion: Studies in Greek philosophy and its continuation offered to Professor C. J. de Vogel. Assen: Van Gorcum.

Perry, B. E. (2016). The early Greek capacity for viewing things separately. Illinois Classical Studies, 41(2), 477-494.

Press, G. A. (2000). Who speaks for Plato? Studies in Platonic anonymity. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

Rhodes, P. J. (2019). Herodotus: Histories, Book V. Liverpool: Liverpool University Press.

Santoro, F. (2011). Ta Semata: On a genealogy of the idea of ontological categories. In Néstor-Luis Cordero (Ed.), Parmenides, venerable and awesome (Plato, Theaetetus 183e). Las Vegas: Parmenides Publishing.

Semenzato, C. (2017). A l’écoute des Muses en Grèce archaïque. De Gruyter.

Taran, L. (1965). Parmenides: A text with translation, commentary, and critical essays. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Tarrant, H. (2000). Where Plato speaks: Reflections on an Ancient debate. In Hayden W. Ausland et al. (Eds.), Who speaks for Plato? Studies in Platonic anonymity. Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.

Thesleff, H. (1999). Studies in Plato’s Two-Level Model. Helsinki: Societas Scientarum Fennica.

Thesleff, H. (2000). The philosopher conducting dialectic. In Hayden W. Ausland et al. (Eds.), Who speaks for Plato? Studies in Platonic anonymity. Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.

Thesleff, H. (2002). An introduction to studies in Plato’s Two-Level Model. Journal of the International Plato Society, 3, 20.

Traglia, A. (1955). Per la storia dei termini onoma e rhema e sul valore di onoma, logos ed epos in Eraclito e in Parmenide.  In Contributi dell'Istituto di Storia della Filosofia dell'Università di Bari (pp. 147-161). Trani: Vecchi & C. Editori.

Verdenius, W. J. (1949). Parmenides’ conception of light. Mnemosyne, 2(2), 116-131.

Verity, A. (2007). Pindar the complete Odes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Vick, G. R. (1971). Heidegger’s linguistic rehabilitation of Parmenides’ “being”. American Philosophical Quarterly, 8(2), 139-150.

Vlastos, G. (2008). in A. P. D. Mourelatos, The route of Parmenides. Las Vegas: Parmenides Publishing.

von Fritz, K. (1974). Nous, Noein, and their derivatives in pre-Socratic philosophy (excluding Anaxagoras). In The pre-Socratics: A collection of critical essays. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

West, E. J. M. (2000). Why Plato does not speak? In Hayden W. Ausland et al. (Eds.), Who speaks for Plato? Studies in Platonic anonymity. Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.

West, E. J. M. (1995). Plato’s Audiences, or How Plato replies to the fifth-century intellectual mistrust of letters. In Francisco J. Gonzalez (Ed.), The third way: New directions in Platonic studies. Rowman & Littlefield.

Woodbury, L. (1958). Parmenides on names. Harvard Studies in Classical Philology, 63, 145-160.

Woodbury, L. (1986). Parmenides on naming by mortal men: Fr. B8.53-56. Ancient Philosophy, 6, 1-13.


© Center for Open Access in Science